Value Maximization, Stakeholder Theory,
and the Corporate Objective Function
Michael C. Jensen The
Monitor Group and Harvard Business School MJensen@hbs.edu
Abstract
This
paper examines the role of the corporate objective function in corporate productivity
and efficiency, social welfare, and the accountability of managers and
directors. I argue that since it is logically impossible to maximize in more
than one dimension, purposeful behavior requires a single valued objective
function. Two hundred years of work in economics and finance implies that in
the absence of externalities and monopoly (and when all goods are priced),
social welfare is maximized when each firm in an economy maximizes its total
market value. Total value is not just the value of the equity but also includes
the market values of all other financial claims including debt, preferred
stock, and warrants. In sharp contrast stakeholder theory, argues that managers
should make decisions so as to take account of the interests of all stakeholders
in a firm (including not only financial claimants, but also employees,
customers, communities, governmental officials, and under some interpretations
the environment, terrorists, and blackmailers). Because the advocates of stakeholder
theory refuse to specify how to make the necessary tradeoffs among these competing
interests they leave managers with a theory that makes it impossible for them
to make purposeful decisions. With no way to keep score, stakeholder theory
makes managers unaccountable for their actions. It seems clear that such a
theory can be attractive to the self-interest of managers and directors. Creating
value takes more than acceptance of value maximization as the organizational
objective. As a statement of corporate purpose or vision, value maximization is
not likely to tap into the energy and enthusiasm of employees and managers to
create value. Seen in this light, change in long-term market value becomes the
scorecard that managers, directors, and others use to assess success or failure
of the organization. The choice of value maximization as the corporate
scorecard must be complemented by a corporate vision, strategy and tactics that
unite participants in the organization in its struggle for dominance in its
competitive arena. A firm cannot maximize value if it ignores the interest of
its stakeholders. I offer a proposal to clarify what I believe is the proper
relation between value maximization and stakeholder theory. I call it
enlightened value maximization, and it is identical to what I call enlightened
stakeholder theory. Enlightened value maximization utilizes much of the
structure of stakeholder theory but accepts maximization of the long run value
of the firm as the criterion for making the requisite tradeoffs among its
stakeholders. Managers, directors, strategists, and management scientists can
benefit from enlightened stakeholder theory. Enlightened stakeholder theory
specifies long-term value maximization or value seeking as the firm’s objective
and therefore solves the problems that arise from the multiple objectives that accompany
traditional stakeholder theory. I also discuss the Balanced Scorecard, the
managerial equivalent of stakeholder theory. The same conclusions hold.
Balanced Scorecard theory is flawed because it presents managers with a
scorecard which gives no score--that is, no single-valued measure of how they
have performed. Thus managers evaluated with such a system (which can easily
have two dozen measures and provides no information on the tradeoffs between
them) have no way to make principled or purposeful decisions. The solution is
to define a true (single dimensional) score for measuring performance for the
organization or division (and it must be consistent with the organization's
strategy). Given this we then encourage managers to use measures of the drivers
of performance to understand better how to maximize their score. And as long as
their score is defined properly, (and for lower levels in the organization it
will generally not be value) this will enhance their contribution to the firm. Keywords:
Value Maximization, Stakeholder Theory, Balanced Scorecard, Multiple Objectives,
Social Welfare, Social Responsibility, Corporate Objective Function, Corporate Purpose,
Tradeoffs, Corporate Governance, Strategy, Special Interest Groups, Social Responsibility.
VALUE MAXIMIZATION, STAKEHOLDER THEORY, AND THE CORPORATE OBJECTIVE
FUNCTION
by Michael C. Jensen, The Monitor Group and Harvard
Business School*
In
most industrialized nations today, economists, management scholars, policy makers,
corporate executives, and spe- cial interest groups are engaged in a question:
What are we trying to accomplish? Or, to put the same question in more concrete
terms: How do we keep score? When all is said and done, how do we measure
better versus worse? At the economy-wide or social level, the issue is this: If
we could dictate the criterion or objective function to be maximized by firms
(and thus the performance criterion by which corporate execu- tives choose
among alternative policy options), what would it be? Or, to put the issue even
more simply: How do we want the firms in our economy to measure their own
performance? How do we want them to determine what is better versus worse? Most
economists would answer simply that managers must have a criterion for
evaluating perfor- mance and deciding between alternative courses of action,
and that the criterion should be maximization of the long-term market value of
the firm. (And “firm value,” by the way, means not just the value of the equity,
but the sum of the values of all financial claims on the firm—debt,
warrants, and preferred stock, as well as equity.) This Value Maximization proposition
has its roots in 200 years of research in economics and finance. The main
contender to value maximization as the corporate objective is called
“stakeholder theory.” Stakeholder theory says that managers should make decisions
that take account of the interests of all the stakeholders in a firm.
Stakeholders include all high-stakes debate over corporate governance. In some
scholarly and business circles, the discussion focuses mainly on questions of
policies and proce- dures designed to improve oversight of corporate managers
by boards of directors. But at the heart of the current global corporate
governance debate is a remarkable division of opinion about the fundamen- tal
purpose of the corporation. Much of the discord can be traced to the complexity
of the issues and to the strength of the conflicting interests that are likely to
be affected by the outcome. But also fueling the controversy are political,
social, evolutionary, and emotional forces that we don’t usually think of as operating
in the domain of business and economics. These forces serve to reinforce a
model of corporate behavior that draws on concepts of “family” and “tribe.” And
as I argue in this paper, this model is an anachronism—a holdover from an
earlier period of human development that nevertheless continues to cause much
confusion among corporate managers about what it is that they and their
organizations are supposed to do. At the level of the individual organization,
the most basic issue of governance is the following. Every organization has to
ask and answer the individuals or groups who can substantially affect, or be
affected by, the welfare of the firm—a category that includes not only the
financial claimholders, but also employees, customers, communities, and gov- ernment
officials.1 In contrast to the grounding of value
maximization in economics, stakeholder theory has its roots in sociology,
organizational behavior, the politics of special interests, and, as I will
discuss below, managerial self-interest. The theory is now popular and has
received the formal endorsement of many professional organizations, special
interest groups, and governmental bodies, including the current British
government.2 But, as I argue in this paper,
stakeholder theory should not be viewed as a legitimate contender to value
maximization because it fails to provide a complete specification of the
corpo- rate purpose or objective function. To put the matter more concretely,
whereas value maximiza- tion provides corporate managers with a single objective,
stakeholder theory directs corporate managers to serve “many masters.” And, to
para- phrase the old adage, when there are many masters, all end up being
shortchanged. Without the clarity of mission provided by a single-valued objective
function, companies embracing stake- holder theory will experience managerial
confu- sion, conflict, inefficiency, and perhaps even competitive failure. And
the same fate is likely to be visited on those companies that use the so- called
“Balanced Scorecard” approach—the mana- gerial equivalent of stakeholder
theory—as a performance measurement system. But if stakeholder theory and the
Balanced Scorecard can destroy value by obscuring the over- riding corporate
goal, does that mean they have no legitimate corporate uses? And can corporate
man- agers succeed by simply holding up value maximi- zation as the goal and
ignoring their stakeholders? The answer to both is an emphatic no. In order to maximize
value, corporate managers must not only satisfy, but enlist the support of, all
corporate stakeholders—customers, employees, managers, suppliers, local
communities. Top management plays a critical role in this function through its
leadership and effectiveness in creating, projecting, and sustain- ing the
company’s strategic vision. And even if the Balanced Scorecard is likely to be
counterproductive as a performance evaluation and reward system, the process
of creating the scorecard can add significant value by helping managers
understand both the company’s strategy and the drivers of value in their businesses.
With this in mind, I clarify what I believe is the proper relation between
value maximization and stakeholder theory by proposing a (somewhat) new corporate
objective function. I call it enlightened value maximization, and it is
identical to what I call enlightened stakeholder theory. Enlightened
value maximization uses much of the structure of stake- holder theory but
accepts maximization of the long- run value of the firm as the criterion for
making the requisite tradeoffs among its stakeholders. Enlight- ened
stakeholder theory, while focusing attention on meeting the demands of all
important corporate constituencies, specifies long-term value maximiza- tion as
the firm’s objective. In so doing, it solves the problems arising from the
multiple objectives that accompany traditional stakeholder theory by giving managers
a clear way to think about and make the tradeoffs among corporate stakeholders.
The answers to the questions of how managers should define better vs. worse,
and how managers in fact do define it, have important implications for social
welfare. Indeed, the answers provide the business equivalent of the medical
profession’s Hippocratic Oath. It is an indication of the infancy of the
science of management that so many in the world’s business schools, as well as
in professional business organizations, seem to understand so little of the
fundamental issues in contention. With this introduction of the issues, let me
now move to a detailed examination of value maximiza- tion and stakeholder
theory.
THE
LOGICAL STRUCTURE OF THE PROBLEM
In
discussing whether firms should maximize value or not, we must separate two
distinct issues: 1. Should the firm have a single-valued objective? 2. And, if
so, should that objective be value maximization or something else (for example,
main- taining employment or improving the environment)? The debate over whether
corporations should maximize value or act in the interests of their stakeholders
is generally couched in terms of the second issue, and is often mistakenly
framed as stockholders versus stakeholders. The real conflict here,
though this is rarely stated or even recognized, is over the first issue—that
is, whether the firm should have a single-valued objective function or scorecard.
The failure to frame the problem in this way has contributed greatly to
widespread misun- derstanding and contentiousness. What is commonly known as
stakeholder theory, while not totally without content, is fundamentally flawed
because it violates the proposition that a single-valued objective is a
prerequisite for purpose- ful or rational behavior by any organization. In particular
a firm that adopts stakeholder theory will be handicapped in the competition
for survival because, as a basis for action, stakeholder theory politicizes the
corporation and leaves its managers empowered to exercise their own preferences
in spending the firm’s resources.
Issue
#1: Purposeful Behavior Requires the Existence of a Single-Valued
Objective Function.
Consider
a firm that wishes to increase both its current-year profits and its market
share. Assume, as shown in Figure 1, that over some range of values of market
share, profits increase. But, at some point, increases in market share come
only at the expense of reduced current-year profits—say, because increased expenditures
on R&D and advertising, or price reduc- tions to increase market share,
reduce this year’s profit. Therefore, it is not logically possible to speak of maximizing
both market share and profits. In this situation, it is impossible for a
manager to decide on the level of R&D, advertising, or price reductions
because he or she is faced with the need to make tradeoffs between the two
“goods”—profits and market share—but has no way to do so. While the
manager knows that the firm should be at the point of maximum profits or
maximum market share (or somewhere between them), there is no purpose- ful way
to decide where to be in the area in which the firm can obtain more of one good
only by giving up some of the other.
Multiple
Objectives Is No Objective
It
is logically impossible to maximize in more than one dimension at the same time
unless the dimensions are what are known as “monotonic transformations” of one
another. Thus, telling a manager to maximize current profits, market share, future
growth in profits, and anything else one pleases will leave that manager with
no way to make a reasoned decision. In effect, it leaves the manager with no
objective. The result will be confusion and a lack of purpose that will
handicap the firm in its competition for survival.3
A company can resolve this ambiguity by speci- fying the tradeoffs among the
various dimensions, and doing so amounts to specifying an overall objective
such as V= f(x, y, …) that explicitly incor- porates the effects
of decisions on all the perfor- mance criteria—all the goods or bads
(denoted by (x, y, …)) that can affect the firm (such as cash flow, risk,
and so on). At this point, the logic above does not specify what V is.
It could be anything the board of directors chooses, such as employment, sales,
or growth in output. But, as I argue below, social welfare and survival will
severely constrain the boards’ choices. Nothing in the analysis so far has said
that the objective function f must be well behaved and easy to maximize.
If the function is non-monotonic, or even chaotic, it makes it more difficult
for managers to find the overall maximum. (For example, as I discuss later, the
relationship between the value of the firm and a company’s current earnings and
investors’ expectations about its future earnings and investment expenditures
will often be difficult to formulate with much precision.) But even in these situations,
the meaning of “better” or “worse” is defined, and managers and their monitors
have a “principled”—that is, an objective and theoretically consistent—basis
for choosing and auditing decisions. Their choices are not just a matter of
their own personal preferences among various goods and bads. Given managers’
uncertainty about the exact specification of the objective function f,
it is perhaps better to call the objective function “value seeking” rather than
value maximization. This way one avoids the confusion that arises when some
argue that maximizing is difficult or impossible if the world is structured in
sufficiently complicated ways.4 It is not necessary that we be able to
maximize, only that we can tell when we are getting better—that is moving in
the right direction.
Issue
#2: Total Firm Value Maximization Makes Society Better Off.
Given
that a firm must have a single objective that tells us what is better and what
is worse, we then must face the issue of what that definition of better is.
Even though the single objective will always be a complicated function of many
different goods or bads, the short answer to the question is that 200 years’
worth of work in economics and finance indicate that social welfare is
maximized when all firms in an economy attempt to maximize their own total firm
value. The intuition behind this criterion is simple: that value is created—and
when I say “value” I mean “social” value—whenever a firm produces an output, or
set of outputs, that is valued by its customers at more than the value of the
inputs it consumes (as valued by their suppli- ers) in the production of the
outputs. Firm value is simply the long-term market value of this expected
stream of benefits. To be sure, there are circumstances when the value-maximizing
criterion does not maximize social welfare—notably, when there are monopolies
or “externalities.” Monopolies tend to charge prices that are too high,
resulting in less than the socially optimal levels of production. By
“externalities,” economists mean situations in which decision-mak- ers do not
bear the full cost or benefit consequences of their choices or actions.
Examples are cases of air or water pollution in which a firm adds pollution to the
environment without having to purchase the right to do so from the parties
giving up the clean air or water. There can be no externalities as long as alienable
property rights in all physical assets are defined and assigned to some private
individual or firm. Thus, the solution to these problems lies not in telling
firms to maximize something other than profits, but in defining and then
assigning to some private entity the alienable decision rights necessary to
eliminate the externalities.5 In any case, resolving externality and
monopoly problems, as I will discuss later, is the legitimate domain of the
government in its rule-setting function.6 Maximizing the total market value of
the firm— that is, the sum of the market values of the equity, debt and any
other contingent claims outstanding on the firm—is the objective function that
will guide managers in making the optimal tradeoffs among multiple
constituencies (or stakeholders). It tells the firm to spend an additional
dollar of resources to satisfy the desires of each constituency as long as that
constituency values the result at more than a dollar. In this case, the payoff
to the firm from that invest- ment of resources is at least a dollar (in terms
of market value). Although there are many single- valued objective functions
that could guide a firm’s managers in their decisions, value maximization is an
important one because it leads under most conditions to the maximization of
social welfare. But let’s look more closely at this.
VALUE
MAXIMIZING AND SOCIAL WELFARE
Much
of the discussion in policy circles about the proper corporate objective casts
the issue in terms of the conflict among various constituencies, or
“stakeholders,” in the corporation. The question then becomes whether
shareholders should be held in higher regard than other constituencies, such as
employees, customers, creditors, and so on. But it is both unproductive and
incorrect to frame the issue in this manner. The real issue is what corporate behavior
will get the most out of society’s limited resources—or equivalently, what
behavior will re- sult in the least social waste—not whether one group is or
should be more privileged than another.
Profit
Maximization: A Simplified Case
To
see how value maximization leads to a socially efficient solution, let’s first
consider an objective function, profit maximization, in a world in which all
production runs are infinite and cash flow streams are level and perpetual.
This scenario with level and perpetual streams allows us to ignore the complexity
introduced by the tradeoffs between current and future-year profits (or, more
accurately, cash flows). Consider now the social welfare effects of a firm’s
decision to take resources out of the economy in the form of labor hours,
capital, or materials purchased voluntarily from their owners in single-price
markets. The firm uses these inputs to produce outputs of goods or services
that are then sold to consumers through voluntary transactions in single-price
markets. In this simple situation, a company that takes inputs out of the
economy and puts its output of goods and services back into the economy
increases aggre- gate welfare if the prices at which it sells the goods more than
cover the costs it incurs in purchasing the inputs (including, of course, the
cost of the capital the firm is using). Clearly the firm should expand its
output as long as an additional dollar of resources taken out of the economy is
valued by the consumers of the incremental product at more than a dollar. Note
that it is precisely because profit is the amount by which revenues exceed
costs—by which the value of output exceeds the value of inputs—that profit
maximization7 leads to an efficient social outcome.8
Because the transactions are voluntary, we know that the owners of the inputs
value them at a level less than or equal to the price the firm pays— otherwise
they wouldn’t sell them. Therefore, as long as there are no negative
externalities in the input factor markets,9 the opportunity cost to society of
those inputs is no higher than the total cost to the firm of acquiring them. I
say “no higher” because some suppliers of inputs to the firm are able to earn “rents”
by obtaining prices higher than the value of the goods to them. But such rents
do not represent social costs, only transfers of wealth to those suppli- ers.
Likewise, as long as there are no externalities in the output markets, the
value to society of the goods and services produced by the firm is at least as
great as the price the firm receives for the sale of those goods and services.
If this were not true, the individuals purchasing them would not do so. Again, as
in the case of producer surplus on inputs, the benefit to society is higher to
the extent that con- sumer surplus exists (that is, to the extent that some consumers
are able to purchase the output at prices lower than the value to them). In
sum, when the a company acquires an additional unit of any input(s) to produce
an addi- tional unit of any output, it increases social welfare by at least the
amount of its profit—the difference between the value of the output and the
cost of the input(s) required in producing it.10 And
thus the signals to the management are clear: Continue to expand purchases of
inputs and sell the resulting outputs as long as an additional dollar of inputs
generates sales of at least a dollar.
Value
and Tradeoffs through Time
In
a world in which cash flows, profits, and costs are not uniform over time,
managers must deal with the tradeoffs of these items through time. A common case
is when a company’s capital investment comes in lumps that have to be funded up
front, while production and revenue occurs in the future. Know- ing whether
society will be benefited or harmed requires knowing whether the future output
will be valuable enough to offset the cost of having people give up their
labor, capital, and material inputs in the present. Interest rates help us make
this decision by telling us the cost of giving up a unit of a good today for
receipt at some time in the future. So long as people take advantage of the
opportunity to borrow or lend at a given interest rate, that rate determines the
value of moving a marginal dollar of resources (inputs or consumption goods)
forward or backward in time.11 In this world, individuals are as well
off as possible if they maximize their wealth as measured by the discounted
present value of all future claims. In addition to interest rates, managers
also need to take into account the risk of their investments and the premium
the market charges for bearing such risk. But, when we add uncertainty and risk
into the equation, nothing of major importance is changed in this proposition
as long as there are capital markets in which the individual can buy and sell
risk at a given price. In this case, it is the risk-adjusted interest rate that
is used in calculating the market value of risky claims. The corporate
objective function that maximizes social welfare thus becomes “maximize current
total firm market value.” It tells firms to expand output and investment to the
point where the present market value of the firm is at a maximum.12
STAKEHOLDER
THEORY
To
the extent that stakeholder theory says that firms should pay attention to all
their constituencies, the theory is unassailable. Taken this far stakeholder theory
is completely consistent with value maximi- zation or value-seeking behavior,
which implies that managers must pay attention to all constituencies that can
affect the value of the firm. But there is more to the stakeholder story than this.
Any theory of corporate decision-making must tell the decision-makers—in this
case, managers and boards of directors—how to choose among multiple constituencies
with competing and, in some cases, conflicting interests. Customers want low
prices, high quality, and full service. Employees want high wages, high-quality
working conditions, and fringe benefits, including vacations, medical benefits,
and pensions. Suppliers of capital want low risk and high returns. Communities
want high charitable contribu- tions, social expenditures by companies to
benefit the community at large, increased local investment, and stable
employment. And so it goes with every conceivable constituency. Obviously any
decision criterion—and the objective function is at the core of any decision
criterion—must specify how to make the tradeoffs between these demands.
The
Specification of Tradeoffs and the Incompleteness of Stakeholder
Theory
Value
maximization (or value seeking) provides the following answer to the tradeoff
question: Spend an additional dollar on any constituency provided the long-term
value added to the firm from such expenditure is a dollar or more. Stakeholder
theory, by contrast,13 contains no conceptual specification of
how to make the tradeoffs among stakeholders. And as I argue below, it is this
failure to provide a criterion for making such tradeoffs, or even to
acknowledge the need for them, that makes stakeholder theory a prescription for
destroying firm value and reducing social welfare. This failure also helps
explains the theory’s remarkable popularity.
Implications
for Managers and Directors
Because
stakeholder theory leaves boards of directors and executives in firms with no
principled criterion for decision-making, companies that try to follow the
dictates of stakeholder theory will even- tually fail if they are competing
with firms that are aiming to maximize value. If this is true, why do so many
managers and directors of corporations em- brace stakeholder theory? One answer
lies in their personal short-run inter- ests. By failing to provide a
definition of better, stakeholder theory effectively leaves managers and directors
unaccountable for their stewardship of the firm’s resources. Without criteria
for performance, managers cannot be evaluated in any principled way. Therefore,
stakeholder theory plays into the hands of managers by allowing them to pursue
their own interests at the expense of the firm’s financial claimants and
society at large. It allows managers and directors to devote the firm’s
resources to their own favorite causes—the environment, art, cities, medical
research— without being held accountable for the effect of such expenditures on
firm value. (And this can be true even though managers may not consciously
recognize that adopting stakeholder theory leaves them unaccount- able—especially,
for example when such managers have a strong personal interest in social
issues.) By expanding the power of managers in this unproductive way,
stakeholder theory increases agency costs in the economic system. And since it
expands the power of managers, it is not surprising that stakeholder theory receives
substantial support from them. In this sense, then, stakeholder theory can be
seen as gutting the foundations of the firm’s internal control systems. By
“internal control systems,” I mean mainly the corporate performance measurement
and evalua- tion systems that, when properly designed, provide strong
incentives for value-increasing behavior. There is simply no principled way
within the stakeholder construct (which fails to specify what better is) that anyone
could say that a manager has done a good or bad job. Stakeholder theory
supplants or weakens the power of such control systems by giving managers more
power to do whatever they want, subject only to constraints that are imposed by
forces outside the firm—by the financial markets, the market for corpo- rate
control (e.g., the market for hostile takeovers), and, when all else fails, the
product markets. Thus, having observed the efforts of stake- holder theory
advocates to weaken internal control systems, it is not surprising to see the
theory being used to argue for government restrictions, such as state
anti-takeover provisions, on financial markets and the market for corporate
control. These markets are driven by value maximization and will limit the damage
that can be done by managers who adopt stakeholder theory. And, as illustrated
by the 1990s campaigns against globalization and free trade, the stakeholder
argument is also being used to restrict product-market competition as well. But
there is something deeper than self-interest— something rooted in the evolution
of the human psyche— that is driving our attraction to stakeholder theory.
FAMILIES
VERSUS MARKETS: THE ROOTS OF STAKEHOLDER THEORY
Stakeholder
theory taps into the deep emotional commitment of most individuals to the
family and tribe. For tens of thousands of years, those of our ancestors who
had little respect for or loyalty to the family, band, or tribe were much less
likely to survive than those who did. In the last few hundred years, we have
experi- enced the emergence of a market exchange system of prices and the
private property rights on which they are based. This system of voluntary and
decentralized coordination of human action has brought huge increases in human
welfare and freedom of action. As Friedrich von Hayek points out, we are generally
unaware of the functioning of these market systems because no single mind
invented or de- signed them—and because they work in very com- plicated and
subtle ways.
In
Hayek’s words: We are led—for example, by the pricing system in
market exchange—to do things by circumstances of which we are largely
unaware and which produce results that we do not intend. In our economic
activities we do not know the needs which we satisfy nor the sources
of the things which we get. Almost all of us serve people whom we do not
know, and even of whose existence we are ignorant; and we in turn constantly
live on the services of other people of whom we know nothing. All this
is possible because we stand in a great framework of institutions and
traditions— economic, legal, moral—into which we fit ourselves by
obeying certain rules of conduct that we never made, and which we have
never understood in the sense in which we understand how the things that
we manufacture function.14
Moreover,
these systems operate in ways that limit the options of the small group or
family, and these constraints are neither well understood nor instinctively
welcomed by individuals. Many people are drawn to stakeholder theory through
their evo- lutionary attachment to the small group and the family.
As
Hayek puts it: Constraints on the practices of the small group, it
must be emphasized and repeated, are hated. For, as we shall see,
the individual following them, even though he depends on them for life,
does not and usually cannot understand how they function or how
they benefit him. He knows so many objects that seem desirable but for
which he is not permitted to grasp, and he cannot see how other
beneficial fea- tures of his environment depend on the discipline to
which he is forced to submit—a discipline forbidding him to reach out
for these same appealing objects. Disliking these constraints so much,
we hardly can be said to have selected them; rather, these constraints
selected us: they enabled us to survive.15
Thus we have a system in which human beings must simultaneously exist in two
orders, what Hayek calls the “micro-cosmos” and the “macro-cosmos”:
Moreover,
the structures of the extended order are made up not only of individuals
but also of many, often overlapping, suborders within which old in- stinctual
responses, such as solidarity and altruism, continue to retain some
importance by assisting voluntary collaboration, even though they are
inca- pable, by themselves, of creating a basis for the more extended
order. Part of our present difficulty is that we must constantly adjust
our lives, our thoughts and our emotions, in order to live
simultaneously within different kinds of orders according to different
rules. If we were to apply the unmodified, uncurbed rules of the
micro-cosmos (i.e. of the small band or troop, or of, say, our families)
to the macro-cosmos (our wider civilization), as our instincts and
sentimental yearnings often make us wish to do, we would destroy it.
Yet if we were always to apply the rules of the extended order to our
more intimate groupings, we would crush them. So we must learn to live
in two sorts of worlds at once. To apply the name ‘society’ to both,
or even to either, is hardly of any use, and can be most misleading.16
Stakeholder
theory taps into this confusion and antagonism towards markets and relaxes
constraints on the small group in ways that are damaging to society as a whole
and (in the long run) to the small group itself. Such deeply rooted and
generally unrecognized con- flict between allegiances to family and tribe and
what is good for society as whole has had a major impact on our evolution. And
in this case, the conflict does not end up serving our long-run collective
interests.[1]
ENLIGHTENED
VALUE MAXIMIZATION AND ENLIGHTENED STAKEHOLDER THEORY
For
those intent on improving management, organizational governance, and
performance, there is a way out of the conflict between value maximiz- ing and
stakeholder theory. It lies in the melding together of what I call “enlightened
value maximiza- tion” and “enlightened stakeholder theory.”
Enlightened
Value Maximization
Enlightened value maximization recognizes that
communication with and motivation of an organization’s managers, employees, and
partners is extremely difficult. What this means in practice is that if we
simply tell all participants in an organization that its sole purpose is to
maximize value, we will not get maximum value for the organization. Value maximization
is not a vision or a strategy or even a purpose; it is the scorecard for the
organization. We must give people enough structure to understand what
maximizing value means so that they can be guided by it and therefore have a
chance to actually achieve it. They must be turned on by the vision or the
strategy in the sense that it taps into some human desire or passion of their
own—for example, a desire to build the world’s best automobile or to create a film
or play that will move people for centuries. All this can be not only
consistent with value seeking, but a major contributor to it. And this brings
us up against the limits of value maximization per se. Value seeking
tells an organiza- tion and its participants how their success in achieving a
vision or in implementing a strategy will be assessed. But value maximizing or
value seeking says nothing about how to create a superior vision or strategy.
Nor does it tell employees or managers how to find or establish initiatives or
ventures that create value. It only tells them how we will measure success in
their activity. Defining what it means to score a goal in football or soccer,
for example, tells the players nothing about how to win the game; it just tells
them how the score will be kept. That is the role of value maximization in
organizational life. It doesn’t tell us how to have a great defense or offense,
or what kind of plays to create, or how much to train and practice, or whom to
hire, and so on. All of these critical functions are part of the competitive
and organiza- tional strategy of any team or organization. Adopting value
creation as the scorekeeping measure does nothing to relieve us of the
responsibility to do all these things and more in order to survive and dominate
our sector of the competitive landscape. This means, for example, that we must
give employees and managers a structure that will help them resist the
temptation to maximize short-term financial performance (as typically measured
by accounting profits or, even worse, earnings per share). Short-term profit
maximization at the ex- pense of long-term value creation is a sure way to destroy
value. This is where enlightened stakeholder theory can play an important role.
We can learn from stakeholder theorists how to lead managers and participants
in an organization to think more gener- ally and creatively about how the
organization’s policies treat all important constituencies of the firm. This
includes not just the stockholders and financial markets, but employees,
customers, suppliers, and the community in which the organization exists. Indeed,
it is a basic principle of enlightened value maximization that we cannot
maximize the long-term market value of an organization if we ignore
or mistreat any important constituency. We cannot create value without good
relations with customers, employees, financial backers, suppliers, regulators,
and communities. But having said that, we can now use the value criterion for
choosing among those competing interests. I say “competing” interests because
no constituency can be given full satisfaction if the firm is to flourish and
survive. Moreover, we can be sure—again, apart from the possibility of
externalities and monopoly power— that using this value criterion will result
in making society as well off as it can be. As stated earlier, resolving
externality and mo- nopoly problems is the legitimate domain of the government
in its rule-setting function. Those who care about resolving monopoly and
externality is- sues will not succeed if they look to corporations to resolve
these issues voluntarily. Companies that try to do so either will be eliminated
by competitors who choose not to be so civic minded, or will survive only by
consuming their economic rents in this manner.
Enlightened
Stakeholder Theory
Enlightened
stakeholder theory is easy to ex- plain. It can make use of most of what
stakeholder theorists offer in the way of processes and audits to measure and
evaluate the firm’s management of its relations with all important
constituencies. Enlight- ened stakeholder theory adds the simple specifica- tion
that the objective function—the overriding goal—of the firm is to maximize
total long-term firm market value. In short, the change in the total long- term
market value of the firm is the scorecard by which success is measured. I say “long-term” market value to recognize
the possibility that financial markets, although forward looking, may not
understand the full implications of a company’s policies until they begin to
show up in cash flows over time. In such cases, management must communicate to
investors the policies’ antici- pated effect on value, and then wait for the
market to catch up and recognize the real value of its decisions as reflected
in increases in market share, customer and employee loyalty, and, finally, cash
flows. Value creation does not mean responding to the day-to-day fluctuations
in a firm’s value. The market is inevitably ignorant of many managerial actions
and opportunities, at least in the short run. In those situations where the
financial markets clearly do not have this private competitive informa- tion,
directors and managers must resist the pres- sures of those markets while
making every effort to communicate their expectations to investors. In this
way, enlightened stakeholder theorists can see that although stockholders are
not some special constituency that ranks above all others, long-term stock
value is an important determinant (along with the value of debt and other
instruments) of total long-term firm value. They would recognize that value
creation gives management a way to assess the tradeoffs that must be made among
competing constituencies, and that it allows for principled decision making
independent of the personal pref- erences of managers and directors. Also
important, managers and directors become accountable for the assets under their
control because the value scorecard provides an objective yardstick against
which their performance can be evaluated.
Measurability and Imperfect Knowledge
It
is important to recognize that none of the above arguments depends on value
being easily observable. Nor do they depend on perfect knowl- edge of the
effects on value of decisions regarding any of a firm’s constituencies. The
world may be complex and difficult to understand. It may leave us in deep
uncertainty about the effects of any decisions we may make. It may be governed
by complex dynamic systems that are difficult to optimize in the usual sense.
But that does not remove the necessity of making choices on a day-to-day basis.
And to do this in a purposeful way we must have a scorecard. The absence of a
scorecard makes it easier for people to engage in value-claiming activities
that satisfy one or more group of stakeholders at the expense of value
creation. We can take random actions, and we can devise decision rules that depend
on superstitions. But none of these is likely to serve us well in the
competition for survival. We must not confuse optimization with value creation
or value seeking. To create value we need not know exactly what maximum value
is and precisely how it can be achieved. What we must do, however, is to set up
our organizations so that managers and employees are clearly motivated to seek
value—to institute those changes and strategies that are most likely to cause
value to rise. To navigate in such a world in anything close to a purposeful way,
we must have a notion of “better,” and value seeking is such a notion. I know of
no other scorecard that will score the game as well as this one. Under most circumstances
and conditions, it tells us when we are getting better, and when we are getting
worse. It is not perfect, but that is the nature of the world.
THE
BALANCED SCORECARD
The
Balanced Scorecard is the managerial equiva- lent of stakeholder theory. Like
stakeholder theory, the notion of a “balanced” scorecard appeals to many, but
it suffers from many of the same flaws. When we use multiple measures on the
balanced scorecard to evaluate the performance of people or business units, we
put managers in the same impos- sible position as managers trying to manage
under stakeholder theory. We are asking them to maximize in more than one
dimension at a time with no idea of the tradeoffs between the measures. As a
result, purposeful decisions cannot be made. The balanced scorecard arose from
the belief of its originators, Robert Kaplan and David Norton, that purely
financial measures of performance are not sufficient to yield effective
management decisions.18
I agree with this conclusion though, as I suggest below, they have
inadvertently confused this with the unstated, but implicit conclusion that
there should never be a single measure of performance. Moreover,
especially at lower levels of an organiza- tion, a single pure
financial measure of performance is unlikely to properly measure a person’s or
even a business unit’s contribution to a company. In the words of Kaplan and
Norton:
The
Balanced Scorecard complements finan- cial measures of past performance
with measures of the drivers of future performance. The objectives and
measures of the scorecard are derived from an organization’s vision
and strategy. The objectives and measures view organizational
performance from four perspectives: financial, customer, internal busi-
ness process, and learning and growth.
.
. .
The Balanced Scorecard expands the set of business unit objectives
beyond summary finan- cial measures. Corporate executives can now mea-
sure how their business units create value for current and future
customers and how they must enhance internal capabilities and the
investment in people, systems, and procedures necessary to improve
future performance. The Balanced Scorecard captures the critical
value-creation activities created by skilled, motivated organiza- tional
participants. While retaining, via the fi- nancial perspective, an
interest in short-term per- formance, the Balanced Scorecard clearly
reveals the value drivers for superior long-term financial and
competitive performance.19 As Kaplan and Norton
go on to say, The measures are balanced between the out- come
measures—the results of past efforts—and the measures that drive future
performance. And the scorecard is balanced between objective
easily quan- tified outcome measures and subjective, somewhat judgmental
performance drivers of the outcome measures…. A good balanced
scorecard should have an appropriate mix of outcomes (lagging indica-
tors) and performance drivers (leading indica- tors) that have been
customized to the business unit’s strategy.”20
The
aim of Kaplan and Norton, then, is to capture both past performance and
expected future performance in scorecards with multiple measures— in fact, as
many as two dozen of them—that are intimately related to the organization’s
strategy.21
And this is where my misgivings about the Balanced Scorecard lie. For an
organization’s strategy to be implemented effectively, each person in the
organi- zation must clearly understand what he or she has to do, how their
performance measures will be con- structed, and how their rewards and
punishments are related to those measures. But, as we saw earlier in the case
of multiple constituencies (or the multiple goals represented in Figure 1),
decision makers cannot make rational choices without some overall single
dimensional objective to be maximized. Given a dozen or two dozen measures and
no sense of the tradeoffs between them, the typical manager will be unable to
behave purposefully, and the result will be confusion. Kaplan and Norton
generally do not deal with the critical issue of how to weight the multiple dimensions
represented by the two-dozen measures on their scorecards. And this is where
problems with the Balanced Scorecard are sure to arise: without specifying what
the tradeoffs are among these two dozen or so different measures, there is no
“balance” in their scorecard. Adding to the potential for confusion, Kaplan and
Norton also offer almost no guidance on the critical issue of how to tie the performance
measurement system to managerial incentives and rewards. Here is their
concluding statement on this important matter: Several approaches may be
attractive to pursue. In the short term, tying incentive compensation of
all senior managers to a balanced set of business unit scorecard
measures will foster commitment to overall organizational goals, rather
than suboptimization within functional departments…Whether such link-
ages should be explicit... or applied judgmentally… will likely vary
from company to company. More knowledge about the benefits and costs of
explicit linkages will undoubtedly continue to be accumu- lated
in the years ahead.22 What the Balanced Scorecard fails to provide, then,
is a clear linkage (and a rationale for that linkage) between the performance
measures and the corporate system of rewards and punishments. In- deed, the
Balanced Scorecard does not provide a scorecard in the traditional sense of the
word. And, to make my point, let me push the sports analogy a little further. A
scorecard in any sport yields a single number that determines the winner among
all contestants. In most sports the person or team with the highest score wins.
Very simply, a scorecard yields a score, not multiple measures of different
dimensions like yards rushing and pass- ing. These latter drivers of
performance affect who wins and who loses, but they do not them- selves
distinguish the winner. To reiterate, the Balanced Scorecard does not yield a
score that would allow us to distinguish winners from losers. For this reason,
the system is best described not as a scorecard, but as a dashboard or
instrument panel. It can tell managers many interesting things about their
business, but it does not give a score for the organization’s performance, or
even for the performance of its business units. As a senior manager of a large
financial institution that spent considerable time implementing a balanced scorecard
system explained to me: “We never fig- ured out how to use the scorecard to
measure performance. We used it to transfer information, a lot of information,
from the divisions to the senior management team. At the end of the day,
however, your performance depended on your ability to meet your targets for
contribution to bottom-line profits.” Thus, because of the lack of a way for
managers to think through the difficult task of determining an unambiguous
performance measure in the Balanced Scorecard system, the result in this case
was a fallback to a single and inadequate financial measure of performance (in
this case, accounting profits)— the very approach that Kaplan and Norton
properly wish to change. The lack of a single one-dimensional measure by which
an organization or department or person will score their performance means
these units or people cannot make purposeful decisions. They cannot do so
because if they do not understand the tradeoffs between the multiple measures,
they cannot know whether they are becoming better off (except in those rare
cases when all measures are increasing in some decision). In sum, the
appropriate measure for the orga- nization is value creation, the change in the
market value of all claims on the firm. And for those organizations that wish a
“flow” measure of value creation on a quarterly or yearly basis, I recommend Economic
Value Added (EVA). But I hasten to add that, as the performance measures are
cascaded down through the organization, neither value cre- ation nor the
year-to-year measure, EVA, is likely to be the proper performance measure at
all levels. To illustrate this point, let’s now look briefly at perfor- mance
measurement for business units.
Measuring
Divisional Performance
The
proper measure for any person or business unit in a multi-divisional company
will be deter- mined mainly by two factors: the company’s strategy and the
actions that the person or division being evaluated can take to contribute to
the success of the strategy. There are two general ways in principle that this
score or objective can be determined: a central- ized way and a decentralized
way. To see this let us begin by distinguishing clearly between the measure of
performance (single dimen- sional) for a unit or person, and the drivers that
the unit or person can use to affect the performance measure. In the
decentralized solution, the organiza- tion determines the appropriate
performance mea- sure for the unit, and it is the person or unit’s responsibility
to figure out what the performance drivers are, how they influence performance,
and how to manage them. The distinction here is the difference between an
outcome (the performance measure) and the inputs or decision variables (the management
of the performance drivers). And man- agers at higher levels in the hierarchy
may be able to help the person or unit to understand what the drivers are and
how to manage them. But this help can only go so far because the specific
knowledge regarding the drivers will generally lie not in head- quarters, but
in the operating units. Therefore, in the end it is the accountable party, not
headquarters, who will generally have the relevant specific knowl- edge and
therefore must determine the drivers, their changing relation to results, and
how to manage them, not headquarters. At the opposite extreme is the completely
centralized solution, in which headquarters will determine the performance
measure by giving the functional form to the unit that lists the drivers and describes
the weight that each driver receives in the determination of the performance
measure. The performance for a period is then determined by calculating the
weighted average of the measures of the drivers for the period.[2] This
solution effectively transfers the job of learning how to create value at all
levels in the organization to the top managers, and leaves the operating
managers only the job of managing the performance drivers that have been dictated
to them by top management. The problem with this approach, however, is that is
likely to work only in a fairly narrow range of circumstances— those cases
where the specific knowledge necessary to understand the details of the
relation between changes in each driver and changes in the perfor- mance
measure lies higher in the hierarchy. Al- though this category may include a
number of very small firms, it will rule out most larger, multidivisional companies,
especially in today’s rapidly changing business environment.
CLOSING
THOUGHTS ON THE BALANCED SCORECARD AND VALUE MAXIMIZATION
In
summary, the Kaplan-Norton Balanced Scorecard is a tool to help managers
understand what creates value in their business. As such, it is a useful
analytical tool, and I join with Kaplan and Norton in urging managers to do the
hard work necessary to understand what creates value in their organization and
how to manage those value drivers. As they put it, …[A] properly constructed
Balanced Scorecard should tell the story of the business unit’s
strategy. It should identify and make explicit the sequence of hypotheses
about the cause-and-effect relationships between outcome measures and
the performance drivers of those outcomes. Every measure selected for
a Balanced Scorecard should be an element in a chain of
cause-and-effect relationships that commu- nicates the meaning of the
business unit’s strategy to the organization.24
But managers are almost inevitably led to try to use the multiple measures of
the Balanced Scorecard as a performance measurement system. And as a performance
measurement system, the Balanced Scorecard will lead to confusion, conflict,
ineffi- ciency, and lack of focus. This is bound to happen as operating
managers guess at what the tradeoffs might be between each of the dimensions of
perfor- mance. And this uncertainty will generally lead to conflicts with
managers at headquarters, who are likely to have different assessments of the
tradeoffs. Such conflicts, besides causing disappointments and confusion about
operating decisions, could also lead to attempts by operating managers to game
the system—by, say, performing well on financial mea- sures while sacrificing
nonfinancial ones. Moreover, there is no logical or principled resolution of
the resulting conflicts unless all the parties come to agreement about what
they are trying to accomplish; and this means specifying how the score is
calcu- lated—in effect, figuring out how the balance in the Balanced Scorecard
is actually attained. As we saw earlier, even if it were possible to come up
with a truly “optimizing” system where all the weights and the tradeoffs among
the multiple measures and drivers were specified—a highly doubt- ful
proposition—reaching agreement between head- quarters and line management over
the proper weighting of the measures and their linkage to the corporate reward
system would be an enormously difficult, if not an impossible, undertaking. In
addi- tion, it would surely be impossible to keep the system continuously
updated so as to reflect all the changes in a dynamic local and worldwide
competi- tive landscape. A 1996 survey of Balanced Scorecard imple- mentations
by Towers Perrin gives a fairly clear indication of the problems that are
likely to arise with it.25 Perhaps most troubling, 70% of the
companies using a scorecard also reported using it for compen- sation—and an
additional 17% were considering doing so. And, not surprisingly, 40% of the respon-
dents said they believed that the large number of measures weakened the
effectiveness of the mea- surement system. What’s more, in their empirical test
of the effects of the balanced scorecard implemen- tation in a global financial
services firm, a 1997 study by Christopher Ittner, David Larcker, and Marshall Meyer
concluded that the first issue their study raises for future research is
“defining precisely what ‘bal- ance’ is and the mechanisms through which ‘bal- ance’
promotes performance.”26 As I have argued in this paper, this
question cannot be answered be- cause “balance” is a term used by Balanced
Scorecard advocates as a substitute for thorough analysis of one of the more
difficult parts of the performance measurement system—the necessity to evaluate
and make tradeoffs. They and others have been seduced by this hurrah word (who
can argue for “unbal- anced”?) into avoiding careful thought on the issues. In
fact, the sooner we get rid of the word “balance” in these discussions, the
better we will be able to sort out the solutions. Balance cannot ever substitute
for having to deal with the difficult issues associated with specifying the
tradeoffs among multiple goods and bads that determine the overall score for an
organization’s success. We must do this to stand a chance of creating an
organizational scoreboard that actually gives a score—which is something every
good scoreboard must do.
Closing
Thoughts on Stakeholder Theory
Stakeholder
theory plays into the hands of special interests that wish to use the resources
of corporations for their own ends. With the wide- spread failure of centrally
planned socialist and communist economies, those who wish to use non- market
forces to reallocate wealth now see great opportunity in the playing field that
stakeholder theory opens to them. Stakeholder theory gives them the appearance
of legitimate political access to the sources of decision-making power in
organizations, and it deprives those organizations of a principled basis for
rejecting those claims. The result is to undermine the foundations of
value-seeking behavior that have enabled markets and capitalism to generate wealth
and high standards of living worldwide. If widely adopted, stakeholder theory
will re- duce social welfare even as its advocates claim to increase it—much as
happened in the failed commu- nist and socialist experiments of the last
century. And, as I pointed out earlier, stakeholder theorists will often have
the active support of managers who wish to throw off the constraints on their
power provided by the value-seeking criterion and its enforcement by capital
markets, the market for corporate control, and product markets. For ex- ample,
stakeholder arguments played an important role in persuading the U.S. courts
and legislatures to limit hostile takeovers through legalization of poison pills
and state control shareholder acts. And we will continue to see more political
action limiting the power of these markets to constrain managers. In sum,
special interest groups will continue to use the arguments of stakeholder
theory to legitimize their positions, and it is in ourcollective interest to
expose the logical fallacy of these arguments.
As a performance measurement system, the Balanced Scorecard will
lead to confusion, conflict, inefficiency, and
lack of focus. This is bound to happen as operating managers guess at
what the tradeoffs might be between each of the dimensions of
performance.
[1] Value
maximization provides the following answer to the tradeoff question: Spend an additional dollar on any constituency
provided the long-term value added to the firm from such expenditure is a dollar or more. Stakeholder theory, by
contrast, contains no conceptual
specification of how to make the tradeoffs among stakeholders.
[2] The Balanced Scorecard is best described not as a
scorecard, but as a dashboard or instrument
panel. It can tell managers many interesting things about their business,
but it does not give a score for the
organization’s performance, or even for the performance of its business units. It does not allow us to distinguish
winners from losers.
No comments :
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.